• Audio

Originalism 101

Now Playing:
Originalism 101

Originalism 101

What do Originalists agree and disagree about? Is Originalism internal to the Constitution? Would the Founders have considered themselves Originalist? Professor Ilan Wurman joins us to discuss the basic principles of the Originalist methodology.

Transcript

NARRATOR: Thanks for joining this episode of the No. 86 lecture series, where we explore the method and purpose of Originalism. Today’s episode features Ilan Wurman, an Associate Professor of Law at the Sandra Day O'Connor College of Law at Arizona State University, where he teaches administrative law and constitutional law. He is the author of A Debt Against the Living: An Introduction to Originalism (Cambridge 2017). As always, the Federalist Society takes no position on particular legal or public policy issues; all expressions of opinion are those of the speaker. PUBLIUS: Can you tell us what Originalism is in a nutshell? ILAN WURMAN: Originalism is the idea that we should interpret the Constitution with its original meaning, with the meaning its words would have had to the Framers who wrote it, and the public that ratified it. But really originalism is an even more fundamental idea: it's the idea that there's a difference between what the law is and what the law ought to be. And this is in fact how we view most laws. All other laws, whether enacted by Congress or treaties or contracts, we first ask what does the law actually say? What does it do? And then it's a separate question whether that's a good law and whether that law ought to be the law. The Constitution, which itself is a law, a law we the people enacted to bind our legal officials, should be interpreted in the same way. When interpreting the Constitution, we first must ask what does it actually say? What does it do? What legal effect does it have? And it's a separate question whether that Constitution is a good constitution. And the way we figure out what the Constitution says is the same way we figure out what any instruction intended for a public audience says. This instruction could be a recipe that you find in your great grandmother's attic that's dated from 1789. How would you interpret a recipe that was intended as an instruction to other chefs and to the public? Well, you would interpret it with a public meaning, not a secret meaning, otherwise it would be a very poor recipe indeed. And you interpret it with the meaning it had at the time to the people who wrote the recipe. After all, if the recipe says to add ingredient X but you don't like ingredient X today, so you take it out and put in ingredient Y. That's not interpreting the Constitution or interpreting the recipe, that would be changing the recipe. The same kind of argument can be made about interpreting laws and the Constitution, more generally. PUBLIUS: So is Originalism itself internal to the Constitution? Does the Constitution itself say anything about how it should be interpreted? ILAN WURMAN: The Constitution itself says nothing at all about how it is to be interpreted, but the Constitution is a law and it should be interpreted just as other laws and other legal instruments are interpreted. How are other legal instruments interpreted in our legal system? They are interpreted by determining what the words mean, by determining the original public meaning of the laws in order to try to ascertain approximately what the intention of the legislature was. That's how we interpret contracts, we try to figure out the intent of the parties by interpreting the meaning of the words that they used. That's how we interpret laws, we try to figure out what Congress tried to do by figuring out what the meaning of the words that Congress used is. Similarly, the Constitution being like these other laws is simply a law enacted by people with intentions and the way we interpret it is through the words those people used and, in particular, the public and objective meanings of those words. PUBLIUS: So after we’ve discovered the original meaning of the Constitution, what’s the next step for an originalist? ILAN WURMAN: Only then do we ask a secondary question, should that law still be the law? These questions are distinct, but ordinarily even when we think a law enacted by Congress isn't a very good law and should be changed, we still feel bound by that law. In other words, we feel bound by Congress's bad laws as well as its good laws, as long as those laws were enacted by a process that we consider sufficient to confer legitimacy on those laws. So in our legal system we believe that so long as a law is enacted by Congress, by two houses of Congress and signed by the President, it is sufficiently legitimate to be binding upon us even if we don't like what the law says. The same kind of argument can be made about the original Constitution. Even if we don't like everything the original Constitution says, even if we don't like all the provisions of the original Constitution as it's been properly amended, even if we don't like all of it, is there some sense in which we are still bound by the entirety of the Constitution? And it seems to me that so long as the Constitution accomplishes the objectives that a constitution must accomplish to be a successful constitution for a free society. If the constitution successfully balances the competing objectives of self-government on the one hand and preservation of liberty on the other, then it seems to me that the Constitution is in fact binding upon future generations. PUBLIUS: But didn’t even the Founders disagree about whether the Constitution should bind future generations? ILAN WURMAN: in defense of living constitutionalism, scholars often invoke this letter that Thomas Jefferson wrote to James Madison in 1789 in which Thomas Jefferson said that the earth belongs to the living, that the dead have neither power nor rights over it. This letter is often quoted for the proposition that we shouldn't be bound by the dead hand of the past, by the dead hand of the Constitution. And that the Constitution should instead be a living, breathing document subject to changing interpretations over time. But what people often forget is Madison's reply to Jefferson and in that reply Madison said, "That if the earth be the gift of nature to the living, then their title can extend to the earth in its natural state only. The improvements made by the dead," Madison said, "form a debt against the living who take the benefit of them. This debt cannot be otherwise discharged than by a proportionate obedience to the will of the authors of the improvement”--by a kind of originalism. So the question for originalists is whether the Constitution is in fact that kind of improvement upon the natural condition of the world that forms a debt against future generations? The Constitution does form this debt if it successfully accomplishes and successfully achieves what a constitution for a free society must achieve to be a good constitution for that society. A constitution for a free society has to balance the competing imperatives of a free society has to balance on the one hand the creation of a regime of self-government but on the other a preservation of a large measure of natural liberty. These two objectives are competing, are in tension with each other, and it is no easy task to establish a constitution that successfully balances them. If our Constitution does successfully balance them, then it is that kind of improvement that Madison described as forming a debt against future generations. PUBLIUS: Do all originalists agree with this defense of originalism? ILAN WURMAN: There are different kinds of defenses of originalism. Some scholars make purely conceptual claims, this is just how language works. And that's probably right, but on the other hand, non-originalists will say that the case for non-originalism entails judges changing the Constitution and needing to update the Constitution. So it doesn't matter that it's just how language works if non-originalists all accept that; they actually want to update the meaning of the Constitution over time. Other originalists thus make normative defenses of the Constitution because an originalist approach would be normatively more desirable because it would lead to better results. In reality, originalists need to make both kinds of defenses, originalists need conceptual defenses and normative defenses. If the non-originalist view is that it doesn't matter how we ordinarily interpret language because judges are in an activity of updating the meaning of the Constitution anyway, there needs to be some normative argument made for why judges should not be changing the meaning of the Constitution. Why we should be bound by the Constitution as written, the Constitution we already have. PUBLIUS: Is there a difference between textualism and originalism? ILAN WURMAN: Many scholars believe that there is a difference between textualism and originalism. If textualism is different from originalism, then I suppose textualism means looking strictly at the text and only at the text to determine what the text means. But how do we determine what texts mean in ordinary documents or in ordinary communication? Well, words only have meaning in context, text only has meaning in context. It helps to know why someone spoke or wrote certain words, it helps to know what purposes they wrote it for, it helps to know what background assumptions that they had, it helps to know the historical context, and the historical background. Well, if all of these tools are useful to figuring out what the text actually means, well then textualism starts to look a lot like originalism, and I'm not sure that there's a difference between the two. PUBLIUS: Is one of originalism’s key virtues that it is more constrained and determinate than alternative methods of constitutional interpretation? ILAN WURMAN: Originalism does not mean that there will be a single determinant right answer every time. Often interpreting the original public meaning of the words leads us to conclude that there is indeterminacy. Words often leave room for vagueness, they leave ambiguities. So texts can be indeterminate. Supporting an originalist interpretation of the Constitution does not mean that we can't recognize these indeterminacies, the question is how to resolve those indeterminacies. It could be, in other words, that the best originalist interpretation of a particular constitutional provision will lead to a range of plausible originalist understandings. It's true that often some originalists will claim that originalism always leads to one determinant right answer and that's a virtue of originalism. But once we grant the existence of indeterminacy, it very well could be that originalism will lead to a range of plausible answers. This range will often exclude prevailing non-originalist interpretations but, nevertheless, it will be capacious enough to include multiple possible interpretations. PUBLIUS: So what is an Originalist to do in the event of indeterminacy? ILAN WURMAN: The Founders themselves recognized that the Constitution would be indeterminate. In Federalist 37, Madison has some beautiful passages about the indeterminacy of language, but they also thought about how to resolve these indeterminacies. The Founders most likely adhered to a concept that we might call liquidation. They would liquidate the meaning, determine the meaning of ambiguous or indeterminate constitutional provisions through or a series of discussions and adjudications. In other words, if there was an uncertainty into the meaning as to the meaning of the Constitution, Congress would debate on what that best meaning should be within the realm of that indeterminacy. It still has to be textually or linguistically plausible. The President could also weigh in on this dispute and the courts could also weigh in on this dispute. And over time over a series of these discussions and adjudications and deliberation, the meaning of the Constitution and its ambiguous parts or its indeterminate parts would become fixed and determined. One example of liquidation, this practice of liquidation, is the debate over the constitutionality of the Bank of the United States. The very first Congresses debated whether Congress had the power to incorporate a national bank. It's not specifically enumerated but it might be necessary and proper to several other powers thus this was indeterminate, it was unclear whether Congress did or did not have this power. Well, Congress and the executive debated and deliberated and concluded when all the constitutional arguments were on the table that Congress does have this power and Congress enacted the National Bank. And James Madison, when he was President two decades later, refused to veto on constitutional grounds the Bank of the United States even though he as a representative had opposed it on constitutional ground. Why? Because he claimed that the question or the constitutionality of the bank had been settled through the series of discussions and adjudications that had occurred in prior Congresses and with prior Presidents. PUBLIUS: Were the Founding Fathers Originalists? ILAN WURMAN: Opponents of originalism often cite this 1985 article by H. Jefferson Powell showing that the Founders did not intend for their intentions to govern. In other words, the Founders weren't themselves originalists and so originalism is self-defeating. But all H. Jefferson Powell shows in this article is that the Founders didn't intend for well their intentions to govern. But originalism is about discerning the original public meaning of the text, not about giving legal effect to the secret intentions of the Founding Fathers. So in that very same article, H. Jefferson Powell actually showed how the Founders expected the Constitution to be interpreted. And it turns out that they expected it to be interpreted by judges discerning the original public meaning of the words PUBLIUS: Isn’t the Constitution outdated? Don’t we need to adapt it to modern circumstances? ILAN WURMAN: Even though the Constitution should be interpreted as other laws are interpreted with their original public meaning, this does not mean that the Constitution can't adapt to future circumstances. In fact, the Framers did at least three things in the Constitution that allowed it to be flexible and adaptable into the future. First the Framers wrote a lot of the constitutional provisions in broad terms. They said Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom of speech. They didn't say Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom to write with quill and parchment thus the First Amendment applies to the Internet. The Fourth Amendment protects against unreasonable searches and seizures. This protects GPS devices placed on automobiles, not just horse-drawn carriages. So through these more expansive standards and principles, the Founders ensured that the Constitution provisions would be able to apply to new circumstances even if the meaning itself did not change. The other great genius of the Founders was that in the Constitution they wrote, they didn't require very much. The Constitution only protects those rights most essential to a free society, the rights to speech, religion and press, the rights of criminal defendants, before they are deprived of life, liberty, or property. But other than that, the Founders left most societal questions to the democratic process precisely because they expected that we would evolve and progress over time. So the Constitution, the Founders wrote, may be a dead Constitution but the democracy that the Constitution created is very much a living and breathing democracy. Third and finally, we can't forget the amendment process. People often lament that the amendment process is so hard to use but the amendment process was supposed to be hard to use. Because the Founders expected us to evolve and circumstances to change in other ways. They wrote the Constitution in varying levels of generality, they gave a lot to the democratic process but the amendment process was reserved only for those most fundamental questions about the nature of regime. And that's in fact how the amendment process was used. The amendment process was used to give us a bill of rights, it was used to abolish slavery, it was used to apply the protections of the federal government against the state governments as well. It was used to enfranchise African-Americans, it was used to enfranchise women. These fundamental changes to the regime is what the amendment process was for and it's what the amendment process has in fact been used for. NARRATOR: Thank you for listening to this episode of the No. 86 Lecture series: Continuing the Conversation in the 85 Federalist Papers about Originalism. The spirit of debate of our Founding Fathers animates all of the No. 86 content, encouraging discussion and critical reflection relative to how each subject is widely understood and taught in law schools and among law students. Subscribe to the No. 86 Lecture series on your favorite podcast platform to have each episode delivered the moment it’s released. You can also go to fedsoc.org/no86 for lectures and videos on Federalism, Separation of Powers, the Judiciary and more. Thanks for listening. See you in class! Transcript [for YouTube - no speaker names/verbatim] Thanks for joining this episode of the No. 86 lecture series, where we explore the method and purpose of Originalism. Today’s episode features Ilan Wurman, an Associate Professor of Law at the Sandra Day O'Connor College of Law at Arizona State University, where he teaches administrative law and constitutional law. He is the author of A Debt Against the Living: An Introduction to Originalism (Cambridge 2017). As always, the Federalist Society takes no position on particular legal or public policy issues; all expressions of opinion are those of the speaker. Can you tell us what Originalism is in a nutshell? Originalism is the idea that we should interpret the Constitution with its original meaning, with the meaning its words would have had to the Framers who wrote it, and the public that ratified it. But really originalism is an even more fundamental idea, it's the idea that there's a difference between what the law is and what the law ought to be. And this is in fact how we view most laws. All other laws, whether enacted by Congress or treaties or contracts, we first ask what does the law actually say? What does it do? And then it's a separate question whether that's a good law and whether that law ought to be the law. The Constitution, which itself is a law, a law we the people enacted to bind our legal officials, should be interpreted in the same way. When interpreting the Constitution, we first must ask what does it actually say? What does it do? What legal effect does it have? And it's a separate question whether that Constitution is a good constitution. And the way we figure out what the Constitution says is the same way we figure out what any instruction intended for a public audience says. This instruction could be a recipe that you find in your great grandmother's attic that's dated from 1789. How would you interpret a recipe that was intended as an instruction to other chefs and to the public? Well, you would interpret it with a public meaning, not a secret meaning, otherwise it would be a very poor recipe indeed. And you interpret it with the meaning it had at the time to the people who wrote the recipe. After all, if the recipe says to add ingredient X but you don't like ingredient X today, so you take it out and put in ingredient Y. That's not interpreting the Constitution or interpreting the recipe, that would be changing the recipe. The same kind of argument can be made about interpreting laws and the Constitution, more generally. So is Originalism itself internal to the Constitution? Does the Constitution itself say anything about how it should be interpreted? The Constitution itself says nothing at all about how it is to be interpreted, but the Constitution is a law and it should be interpreted just as other laws and other legal instruments are interpreted. How are other legal instruments interpreted in our legal system? They are interpreted by determining what the words mean, by determining the original public meaning of the laws in order to try to ascertain approximately what the intention of the legislature was. That's how we interpret contracts, we try to figure out the intent of the parties by interpreting the meaning of the words that they used. That's how we interpret laws, we try to figure out what Congress tried to do by figuring out what the meaning of the words that Congress used is. Similarly, the Constitution being like these other laws is simply a law enacted by people with intentions and the way we interpret it is through the words those people used and, in particular, the public and objective meanings of those words. So after we’ve discovered the original meaning of the Constitution, what’s the next step for an originalist? Only then do we ask a secondary question, should that law still be the law? These questions are distinct, but ordinarily even when we think a law enacted by Congress isn't a very good law and should be changed, we still feel bound by that law. In other words, we feel bound by Congress's bad laws as well as its good laws, as long as those laws were enacted by a process that we consider sufficient to confer legitimacy on those laws. So in our legal system we believe that so long as a law is enacted by Congress, by two houses of Congress and signed by the President, it is sufficiently legitimate to be binding upon us even if we don't like what the law says. The same kind of argument can be made about the original Constitution. Even if we don't like everything the original Constitution says, even if we don't like all the provisions of the original Constitution as it's been properly amended, even if we don't like all of it, is there some sense in which we are still bound by the entirety of the Constitution? And it seems to me that so long as the Constitution accomplishes the objectives that a constitution must accomplish to be a successful constitution for a free society. If the constitution successfully balances the competing objectives of self-government on the one hand and preservation of liberty on the other, then it seems to me that the Constitution is in fact binding upon future generations. But didn’t even the Founders disagree about whether the Constitution should bind future generations? In defense of living constitutionalism, scholars often invoke this letter that Thomas Jefferson wrote to James Madison in 1789 in which Thomas Jefferson said that the earth belongs to the living, that the dead have neither power nor rights over it. This letter is often quoted for the proposition that we shouldn't be bound by the dead hand of the past, by the dead hand of the Constitution. And that the Constitution should instead be a living, breathing document subject to changing interpretations over time. But what people often forget is Madison's reply to Jefferson and in that reply Madison said, "That if the earth be the gift of nature to the living, then their title can extend to the earth in its natural state only. The improvements made by the dead," Madison said, "form a debt against the living who take the benefit of them. This debt cannot be otherwise discharged than by a proportionate obedience to the will of the authors of the improvement”--by a kind of originalism. So the question for originalists is whether the Constitution is in fact that kind of improvement upon the natural condition of the world that forms a debt against future generations? The Constitution does form this debt if it successfully accomplishes and successfully achieves what a constitution for a free society must achieve to be a good constitution for that society. A constitution for a free society has to balance the competing imperatives of a free society has to balance on the one hand the creation of a regime of self-government but on the other a preservation of a large measure of natural liberty. These two objectives are competing, are in tension with each other, and it is no easy task to establish a constitution that successfully balances them. If our Constitution does successfully balance them, then it is that kind of improvement that Madison described as forming a debt against future generations. Do all originalists agree with this defense of originalism? There are different kinds of defenses of originalism. Some scholars make purely conceptual claims, this is just how language works. And that's probably right, but on the other hand, non-originalists will say that the case for non-originalism entails judges changing the Constitution and needing to update the Constitution. So it doesn't matter that it's just how language works if non-originalists all accept that; they actually want to update the meaning of the Constitution over time. Other originalists thus make normative defenses of the Constitution because an originalist approach would be normatively more desirable because it would lead to better results. In reality, originalists need to make both kinds of defenses, originalists need conceptual defenses and normative defenses. If the non-originalist view is that it doesn't matter how we ordinarily interpret language because judges are in an activity of updating the meaning of the Constitution anyway, there needs to be some normative argument made for why judges should not be changing the meaning of the Constitution. Why we should be bound by the Constitution as written, the Constitution we already have. Is there a difference between textualism and originalism? Many scholars believe that there is a difference between textualism and originalism. If textualism is different from originalism, then I suppose textualism means looking strictly at the text and only at the text to determine what the text means. But how do we determine what texts mean in ordinary documents or in ordinary communication? Well, words only have meaning in context, text only has meaning in context. It helps to know why someone spoke or wrote certain words, it helps to know what purposes they wrote it for, it helps to know what background assumptions that they had, it helps to know the historical context, and the historical background. Well, if all of these tools are useful to figuring out what the text actually means, well then textualism starts to look a lot like originalism, and I'm not sure that there's a difference between the two. Is one of originalism’s key virtues that it is more constrained and determinate than alternative methods of constitutional interpretation? Originalism does not mean that there will be a single determinant right answer every time. Often interpreting the original public meaning of the words leads us to conclude that there is indeterminacy. Words often leave room for vagueness, they leave ambiguities. So texts can be indeterminate. Supporting an originalist interpretation of the Constitution does not mean that we can't recognize these indeterminacies, the question is how to resolve those indeterminacies. It could be, in other words, that the best originalist interpretation of a particular constitutional provision will lead to a range of plausible originalist understandings. It's true that often some originalists will claim that originalism always leads to one determinant right answer and that's a virtue of originalism. But once we grant the existence of indeterminacy, it very well could be that originalism will lead to a range of plausible answers. This range will often exclude prevailing non-originalist interpretations but, nevertheless, it will be capacious enough to include multiple possible interpretations. So what is an Originalist to do in the event of indeterminacy? The Founders themselves recognized that the Constitution would be indeterminate. In Federalist 37, Madison has some beautiful passages about the indeterminacy of language, but they also thought about how to resolve these indeterminacies. The Founders most likely adhered to a concept that we might call liquidation. They would liquidate the meaning, determine the meaning of ambiguous or indeterminate constitutional provisions through or a series of discussions and adjudications. In other words, if there was an uncertainty into the meaning as to the meaning of the Constitution, Congress would debate on what that best meaning should be within the realm of that indeterminacy. It still has to be textually or linguistically plausible. The President could also weigh in on this dispute and the courts could also weigh in on this dispute. And over time over a series of these discussions and adjudications and deliberation, the meaning of the Constitution and its ambiguous parts or its indeterminate parts would become fixed and determined. One example of liquidation, this practice of liquidation, is the debate over the constitutionality of the Bank of the United States. The very first Congresses debated whether Congress had the power to incorporate a national bank. It's not specifically enumerated but it might be necessary and proper to several other powers thus this was indeterminate, it was unclear whether Congress did or did not have this power. Well, Congress and the executive debated and deliberated and concluded when all the constitutional arguments were on the table that Congress does have this power and Congress enacted the National Bank. And James Madison, when he was President two decades later, refused to veto on constitutional grounds the Bank of the United States even though he as a representative had opposed it on constitutional ground. Why? Because he claimed that the question or the constitutionality of the bank had been settled through the series of discussions and adjudications that had occurred in prior Congresses and with prior Presidents. Were the Founding Fathers Originalists? Opponents of originalism often cite this 1985 article by H. Jefferson Powell showing that the Founders did not intend for their intentions to govern. In other words, the Founders weren't themselves originalists and so originalism is self-defeating. But all H. Jefferson Powell shows in this article is that the Founders didn't intend for well their intentions to govern. But originalism is about discerning the original public meaning of the text, not about giving legal effect to the secret intentions of the Founding Fathers. So in that very same article, H. Jefferson Powell actually showed how the Founders expected the Constitution to be interpreted. And it turns out that they expected it to be interpreted by judges discerning the original public meaning of the words Isn’t the Constitution outdated? Don’t we need to adapt it to modern circumstances? Even though the Constitution should be interpreted as other laws are interpreted with their original public meaning, this does not mean that the Constitution can't adapt to future circumstances. In fact, the Framers did at least three things in the Constitution that allowed it to be flexible and adaptable into the future. First the Framers wrote a lot of the constitutional provisions in broad terms. They said Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom of speech. They didn't say Congress shall make no law abridging the freedom to write with quill and parchment thus the First Amendment applies to the Internet. The Fourth Amendment protects against unreasonable searches and seizures. This protects GPS devices placed on automobiles, not just horse-drawn carriages. So through these more expansive standards and principles, the Founders ensured that the Constitution provisions would be able to apply to new circumstances even if the meaning itself did not change. The other great genius of the Founders was that in the Constitution they wrote, they didn't require very much. The Constitution only protects those rights most essential to a free society, the rights to speech, religion and press, the rights of criminal defendants, before they are deprived of life, liberty, or property. But other than that, the Founders left most societal questions to the democratic process precisely because they expected that we would evolve and progress over time. So the Constitution, the Founders wrote, may be a dead Constitution but the democracy that the Constitution created is very much a living and breathing democracy. Third and finally, we can't forget the amendment process. People often lament that the amendment process is so hard to use but the amendment process was supposed to be hard to use. Because the Founders expected us to evolve and circumstances to change in other ways. They wrote the Constitution in varying levels of generality, they gave a lot to the democratic process but the amendment process was reserved only for those most fundamental questions about the nature of regime. And that's in fact how the amendment process was used. The amendment process was used to give us a bill of rights, it was used to abolish slavery, it was used to apply the protections of the federal government against the state governments as well. It was used to enfranchise African-Americans, it was used to enfranchise women. These fundamental changes to the regime is what the amendment process was for and it's what the amendment process has in fact been used for. Thank you for listening to this episode of the No. 86 Lecture series: Continuing the Conversation in the 85 Federalist Papers about Originalism. The spirit of debate of our Founding Fathers animates all of the No. 86 content, encouraging discussion and critical reflection relative to how each subject is widely understood and taught in law schools and among law students. Subscribe to the No. 86 Lecture series on your favorite podcast platform to have each episode delivered the moment it’s released. You can also go to fedsoc.org/no86 for lectures and videos on Federalism, Separation of Powers, the Judiciary and more. Thanks for listening. See you in class!

Related Content